*!*Ghomeshi, Jila and Diane Massam. 1994. To Appear, Linguistic Analysis



tải về 302.24 Kb.
trang7/10
Chuyển đổi dữ liệu11.06.2018
Kích302.24 Kb.
#39842
1   2   3   4   5   6   7   8   9   10
principle to other verbs so that applying the same
combinatory principle to new verbs becomes progressively easier.

``Pathbreaking" verbs tend to be generic verbs: typical grammaticalized


markers of tansitivy in many langauges.

They do not have "high transitivity" according to Hopper and


Thompson criteria.  She proposes that their "high transitivity"
 = marked transitivity.  The unmarked case is when the transitivity
is inherent in the verb, whether or not the tense is present oor
past, the mood realis or irrealis, whether the object is animate or
not, etc.

Some nice tables with first verbs.


*!*Orgun, Orhan.  ms.  Turkish direct object (non)incorporation
facts

Word order facts:


 
 new topic  focus predicate background

Accusative objects can occur without case marking.  They


must immediately preced the predicate.

He looks at the general cases: book-reading

Orhan notes that nonreferential constituents tend to occupy
focus positions cross-linguistically.
He argues the stress facts follow from this.

Stress facts are like Persian: V tends to be stressed (unless


a particular argument or adjunct is focused), but
in N-V, it is the N that is stressed.

Orhan notes that hte V can bear contrastive stress but that


lexical compounds cannot bear contrastive stress.

He argues that the position of the bare N is motivated by


parsability concerns since the nominative case is unmarked.
peace happiness brings, both peace and happiness are unmarked. 
Principle: unless case marking gives sufficient clues, SOV order
should be used.  [But that doesn't explain how cases without
subjects are parsed.  It also doesn't explain why adverbs
cannot intervene]

Causativization treats the NV sequence as transitive: therefore


the N seems to be the DO.  (The causee of a transitive verb
appears in dative case) [nice!: check Persian]

Various suffixes, particles and function words can intervene:


question particle:

 Ali today book-int read-past


 Is it a book/books that Ali read today?

Particles expressing contrast, similarity and reduplicated Ns also


intervene:

 Ali kitap bile okur


 Ali book even read-aor

 Ali kitap falan okumaz


 ali book etc. read-neg-aor
 Ali does not read books and the like

 Ali kitap mitap okumaz


 Ali book (redup!) read-neg-aor
 Ali does not read boks and the like.

It is therefore not true, Orhan argues that the NV has any "morphological


integrity."

 Also, the N can be syntactically complex: three book.

*!*Payne, Doris L. Argument Structure and Locs of Affect in the Maasai
External Possession Construction. Paper presented at BLS 23rd 1997 Special
Sesion on Syntax and Semantics in Africa.

Claims: the DO bears TWO semantic roles: possessor and affected.


cites several other cases in which argumetns require two roles.

verb+construction is required:

It is easy to differentiate intransitive  and transitive verbs
since only the latter bear inverse marking (when subject
outranks object on 1>2>3 hierarchy).

Morphology exists for many variations in argument structure


including impersonal passives, middles, antipassives, causatives,
dative and instrumental applicatives.

THE EP Construction:

Possessor i smarked as object on the verb (for 1st and 2nd).
FOr 3rd person, POssessor precedes the Possessed N with no
genitive particle.

She.me.scream  child.nom

``My child is screaming"

take person.nom woman.acc skin.acc

"The person will take the woman's skin."
 
There is no verbal marking for this particular construction: there
is jus tone extra argument than the ver normally allows.
Basic intransitives act as transitives, taking inverses.

it.me.see goat.nom hand.acc


``The goat will see my hand (to my detriment or benefit).

*!*Pine, Julian M, Elena V. M. Lieven and Caroline


F. Rowland.  1998. Comparing different models of the development
of the English verb category.  Linguistics 36 (4)
807-830

>From Abstract:


Great deal of lexical specificity in children's early
use of morphology, auxiliaries, pronoun case marking and
SVO order:  lack of overlap in the verbs
to which different morphological markers were applied,
lack of overlap in the verbs with which different aux's
verbs were used, disproportionate use of "I"; lakof of
overlap in the words which served as subjects and DOs of
transitive verbs.  [they don't address the possibility
that this is just what the child wants to talk about,
not what she is capable of talking about]

``There has been a growing awareness in recent years of the


shortcomings of models of grammatical developemnt based on
the gradual extension of cognitive semantic categories. First,
there is the problem that children's early grammatical knowledge
does not appear to be restricted in the way that such models
would seem to predict (Maratsos 1982, 1988; Maratsos and Chalkley 1980)." pg 3
[early N's for example include walk, kitchen, minute as well
as ball]

...Second,...'agent' cannot be used as a bootstrap into subject


in ergative languages.

Third..children are capable of acquiring linguisitc distinctions


which have little or no semantic base from very early in
development...(e.g. count/mass, N/V) [yikes!]

Valian (1986): the semantic heterogeneity of early lexical


items implies the child is dealing with syntactic categories
such as Det, N, NP, from teh beginning.

Tomasello (1992): lexical constructivist account

Problems with T.: -ing is generalized very early, pronouns seem
to allow more productivity than full NPs; no explanation
for *why* verbs should act as pivots.

With MLUs of 2, English speaking children drop subjects


less often than do Italian children (evidence of pro drop?).:
Valian (1986; 1991).

Radford's (1990) maturational model of acquisition: strict


division between lexical and functional stages: predicts pro drop
and no case marking in early multiword speech (Valian is critiquiing this).

Different morphological markers initially applied to distinct


sets of verbs (Bloom, Lifter and Hafitz 1980, Clark 1996).

Reasonable to assume child has knowledge of abstract pattern


if 1) a relatively large number of instances of the pattern
are attested and 2) the pattern is defined with a particular
verb (assuming, I suppose, that the verb always appears in
the pattern).

Experiment: 12 children: vocabs of 100 words on MacArthur CDI:


therefore were in early stages of multiword speech.
(aged 1;3.7 - 2;0.18)

2 20 minute recording sessions


Productivity:  verbs marked both with and


without a particular morpheme/verbs marked with the morpheme: 
tested whether this was significantly different from zero.

8/12 children showed productivity with the progressive morpheme.

Only two children were productive with the past tense and
third person singular morphemes.

Also, very little overlap in the verbs with which different


inflections were used: i.e. little evidence for category-general
marking.

Any semantic "flavor" in acquisition may be epiphenominal:


it may reflect the semantic distribution bias in the input,
not the learner's bias.

AUXILIARIES (main verb do and aux were differentiated


on distributional grounds)

aux + verb pairs were considered distinct ignorning


tense, polarity and word order.

can, do, be, have accounted for 90.3\% of all


aux+verb combinations.

Overlap = no of verb types occuring both with aux 1 and aux 2/no.


of verb tpes occuring either with aux 1 or aux 2.

None of the children showed overlap that was significantly


different from 0:  ``these results provide very little support
for the attribution of syntactic auxiliary verb and verb categories
to these children" pg 17

Another approach was taken:  Searched for simply


Aux + X: Used Braine's (1976) statistical
criterion for productivity of positional pattern based on
the Binomial theorem (6 different instances in the
same order and 0 instances in a different order or
8 instances in the same order and 1 instance in a different order.
[Shouldn't sample size play an important role here--perhaps
40 minues is not enough time!]

Four chidlren did have one productive positional pattern:


"can't + X" ("can't find it") or "don't + X" ("don't
eat pen").

``These data suggest that children's use of aux + verb


combinations can be accounted for in terms of
a mixture of rote-learned and lexically specific
knowledge and would thus seem to count against a syntactic
performance limitation account [like Valian's]" (pg 18).  (also shows
that children *are* generalizing quite early).

All children had an "I + X" pattern that met Braine's criterion, but


none showed contrastive position of "me".

``These findings count against a


strong version of the Verb-Island Hypothesis since
they suggest that although children's
knowledge of pronoun case-marking may be lexically specific, they
also have at least some lexically specific knowledge of SVO word order which
generalises across different verbs." pg 20.

Subjects did occur overtly often, but 44\% of


the time, they occurred with one verb, the
copula; also "I" was the most common subject; and subject
NPs and object Nps showed little
overlap (raises doubts about the generality of children's knowledge of SVO order)

According to Braine (1987, 1988b): in artificial language


learning: under serial presentation
conditions, subjects readily learn the positions of words
or phrases w.r.t. a marker.
However, they have great difficulty in learning arbitrary dependecies
between *classes* of words.

Pine et al suggest that early grammatical knowledge


may consist of a complex set of
relations between high frequency markers and lexcially and
morphologically defined slots
which reflects the interaction between a distributional
learning mechanism constrained
in the way that Braine (1987) suggests....This would
imply that verb-island effects
are just a speical case of more general
lexical learning effects." pg 26

*!*Pinker, Steven. 1986.  Productivyt and Conservatism


in Language Acquisition.  In William Demopoulos and
Ausonio Marras (eds) Language Learning and Concept Acqusition:
Foundational Issues.  New Jersey: Ablex Publishing.

He gives evidence for conservatism including:

Chidlren learning fixed word order lngs do not
go through a stage of using free word order, but chidlren
learning fre word order lngs do seem to pass through
a stage in which they utter only a subset of
permissible orders (Braine 1976; Brown 1973; Pinker 1984).

Children never invert or put negation after main verbs in questions.

Children do not use auxs in ungrammatical sequences

Contra Conservatism:  errors:

overgeneralization of inflection to exceptional stems

fail to use obligatory closed class morphemes

fail to invert subj and aux (sometimes, while inverting
othet times) and often invert subj and aux for
how come questions (Kuczaj and Brannick 1979).

verb subcategorizations (long list of exceptions given (from Pinker


1984)

performed an experiment with Jess, Annie Zaenen and some others:


taught children novel verbs by performing an action for which
there was no Engish verb and narrating the action
with a single grammatical context (active or passive).
Children were induced to produce the form and also
were tested on comprehension.  The children were between
4 and 5 1/2. [Pretty darn old!]

These chidlren produce the alternative forms  productively

Also showed productivity in creating "to" forms after
they had only heard ditransitives.

*!*Prince, Ellen. 1996. draft.  Constructions and the Syntax


Discourse Interface. University of Pennsylvania

``the association between form and function, is, for all intents


and purposes, an arbitrary one. " pg 2

``the Construction Grammar notion of 'construction,' which


inextricably unites form and function and which is language-particular,
is compatible with what I shall propose but is not sufficient to
account for all the relvant phenomena, since ...[form and function
are not inextricably united...and some generalizations are universal
and not language particular." pg 3.

Generalizations:

form-function associations are arbitrary (single discourse function
can be associated with different syntactic forms, and a single form
with different discourse functions)
naive speakers think of syntactic forms as gestalt 'constructions'
native speakers match syntactically distinct objects crosslinguistically
as reflexes of the 'same construction'

! Universal construction-template: can be mappen onto different syntactic forms


in different languages.

\noindent


! Left Dislocation: 3 different discourse functions:
\eenumsentence{ [My sister got stabbed in her bed]
The landlady, she went up.... \\
removes discourse-new entities from syntactic position disfavored for
discourse-new entities and creates a separate processing unit for them
``She's going to use three groups of mice.  One, she'll feed them
mouse chow...Another, she'll feed them veggies." \\
the entity designated by the initial NP stands in a salient partially-ordered
set relation to some entity or entities already evoked in the discourse
``This is Alice Freed's copy.  My copy of Anttila, I don't know who has it \\
same as above [?] +  the open proposition is info saliently on the speaker's
mind, and the initial NP represents the instantiation of the variable and
the new information."

The same discourse


property in \ex{0a, simplifying processing by
avoiding introducing a discourse-new entity in a position disfavored for
discourse-new entities accounts for the following syntactic forms, too [not
enough explanation here]:
\eenumsentence{ 'Run-on There are a lot of Americans, they can't read.
Resumptive pronoun RC: There are a lot of American's who they can't read.

Also, `analogous' syntactic forms in different languages with different


discourse functions.  e.g. Ward 1995: Italian analog of English existential
there sentences have the discourse function associated with Eng presentational
there sentences and vice versa. [see sentences in paper, page 5]

Resumptive pronouns in Eng: the head is sufficient for the hearer to


evoke the discourse entity; the RC only adds new information about that already
evoked entity.

Resumptive pronouns in Hebrew: (Erteschik-Shir 1989): used when a `restrictive-set'


reading is intended: precisely where the discourse entity cannot be evoked
until the RC is processed:

\eenumsentence{ $<$ in the context where H knows that S bought a dress$>$ \\


Here-is the-dress that-I-bought [e]
$<$ H knows S had 3 dresses in mind originally$>$ \\
Here-is the-dress that-I-bought it.

``no matter how `minimalist' the theory of syntax, we still find the literature


replete with mentions of the 'passive construction,' the 'relative clause construction,'
...etc...Chomsky 1993, after stating explicity that constructions no longer
have any place in syntactic theory, goes on to refer to
sets of linguistic objects
as constructions no less than 8 times.  Thus constructions have clearly
not been eliminated from syntactic metalanguage..." pg 5

``A discoure function associated with a syntactic form in one language may be borrowed


into another language where it is associated with a syntactic form
of that language just in case the two forms..are mapped onto the same abstract Construction-template by the bilingual speaker." pg 7

Same form:  [cp NPk [c' [ip NPj [Vi [vp tj ti ...tk]]]]]:

Topicalization (or "focus movement"):
{These points I'm going to ask Bill to make
the old geezer take up later (Ross 1967 115)

Focus-frame (presupposed) is an open proposition; focus identifies the instantiation


of a variable

The open proposition conveys that a certain entity has a certain attribute;


the focus reprents the value of that attribute, new to the hearer

The Hearer knows that hte entity has the attribute in question


Yiddish movement. 


{Egg creams, you want, bananas you'll get.(Ross 1967: 267)
Less constrained: The info in the open proposition is known or inferrable
to the Hearer:  not limited to values of an attribute: may represent
discourse entity, etc.

Prince: speakers have borrowed the discourse function of


a syntactic form in Yiddish and associated with the syntactic
form called Focus Movement in English.
``Yiddish must have a syntactic form which can be construed as, in some sense,
`the same form' as English Focus Movement and which has the same discourse
function as Yinglish Yiddish Movement" pg 10

`` The syntax of  Yinglish Yiddish Movement...is significantly different from


that of Yiddish Focus-movement...The most obvious difference is
that the subject in ..Yinglish..is preverbal, while the subject in the Yiddish
sentence follows the finite verb." pg 12 (notes this is because of V-2
constraint)

``..what exactly has been borrowed? Certainly not the syntax...


a discourse template function..cannot stand alone...The
form chosen...is that of English Focus-Movement and this choice,
while intuitively obvious, is not at all clear unless we
adopt something along the lines of the Construction-templates
mentioned earlier.. pg 12.

*!*Rappaport Hovav, Malka and Beth Levin. 1995.


The Elasticity of Verb Meaning. In IATL 2: Proceedings
of the Tenth Annual Conference of the Israel Association
for Theoretical Linguistics and the WOrkshop on the Syntax-Semantics
Interface.

Projection Principle theories:  projectionist theories

vs

Constructional Theories



``In projectionist frameworks, verbs with multiple meanings have multiple
lexical representations...If this kind of variation is the rule
rather than the exception, this approach leads to a significant
proliferation of lexical representations.  However, this kind
of variation is not merely associated with individual verbs
but rahter with classes of verbs." pg 2  (But then they suggest
rules)

A lexical entry of a verb is an association of a constant with a lexical


semantic template (the 'thematic core' of Pinker 1989).

Re: section 2: Comparison with Constructional Theories

``Proponents of the constructional approach have suggested that they
present readical departure from projectionist theories. Yet,
a closer look at the details of both theories reveals they have
much in common." pg 4.

``...both theories distinguish between two aspects of verb meaning.


We can call these aspects the structural and the idiosyncratic..." pg 4
 I think you misrepresent
what's been done in the way of restricting which
verbs can occur in which constructions (pg 5).  It's the subject of
much of chapter 2 of my book (particularly 2.4 to the end) and
also of chapter 5.  It's not at all the case that any
construction is supposed to appear with any verb.  That may
be what Hoekstra had in mind (to be honest, I've had a hard
time figuring what he had in mind), but it's clearly false.

 In talking about the ditransitive, the resultative,


the "caused-motion" and the "way" constructions (chapters 6-9),
I also suggest pretty specific semantic constraints that further
constrain which verb classes can occur with each construction.

 The lexicon is not supposed to be just a list of concepts


at all (pg 4)! It is highly structured by non-monotonic
inheritance links of various types that I discuss in
chapters 3 and 4.

 Also I wouldn't say that the meanings of verbs are atomic exactly,


they just aren't amenable to decomposition in terms of a finite set
of primitive elements.  They do have some internal structure:
they specify which participants are obligatorially
expressed, and they make reference of all kinds of frame-specific
knowledge.

 Finally, constructions reside in the lexicon (or better, the


constructicon) alongside words, so it's not clear it makes
sense to contrast the lexicon with "syntax" the way you seem
to on page 4.

Manner verbs: activities

Result verbs: achievements or accomplishments: the complex
nature of the event requires an obligatory DO.
[usually true, but, win]

Assumptions:

Templates may be freely augmented up to other possible templates
Each subevent must be identified by a predicate in the syntax
[What about ditransitives?]
There must be at least one argument XP in the syntax per subevent
 (*Phil swept clean: the second subevent does not have
an associated XP [isn't (very ) clean an XP? ]
Each argument XP must be associated with a subevent.

``because of the template assocaited with a verb like break


cannot be augmented further, no other achieved state or location
can be added to a sentence with break unless it further
specifies the change already lexicalized in the verb as in
Kelly broke the dishes to pieces.
[But Kelly broke the eggs into the bowl. is fine.]

[You don't intend *'s on the first examples of 23 a and b, do you?]

``The acse study here is a first attempt at making explicit
how verb meanings are structured, how these meanigns are
expressed in syntax, and how verbs assume extended meanings" (in
conclusion pg 13)
[ARGH]

BRISSON, C 1994. 


The Licensing of Unexpressed Objects in
ENglish Verbs in CLS 30. 90-102. Is cited as a constructional
approach.   The main claim seems to be: an argument can be left
unexpressed if it understood as 'prototpyical' pg 9.

*!*MacDonald, Maryellen C. Neal J. Pearlmutter, and


Mark S. Seidenberg. 1993. The Lexical Nature of Syntactic
Ambiguity Resolution. ms. USC.

Swinney 1979, Tanenhaus, Leiman & Seidenberg 1979: multiple


senses are accessed.
Swinney claimed senses  exhaustively accessed; others claimed
only most common meanings were accessed.

Some other studies argued that context did have an effect:


at least other words in a sentence could prime a particular
meaning (Simpson 1981, Tabossi et al. 1987). 

Swinney's 2 senses were roughly equi-frequent.


Simpson (1981): reviews studies suggesting that frequency affects


the order in which the  meanings of ambiguous words are accessed.
Highest frequency senses seem to be accessed first.

Assumptions: frequency can affect access; contextual info can result


in activation of only a single meaning;

Syntactic processing has been viewed very differently:


Frazier's Minimal attachment

Studies suggesting lack of context effects in parsing


reduced relatives (vs main verb interpretation)(pg 13):
Ferreira & Clifton
1986, Rayner et al. 1983, etc.

Counterarguments that context effects were obscured by poor stimulus


construction (e.g. McClelland, Tanenhaus, etc).

M: very similar empirical theoretical and methodlogicical issues have


arisen in both lexical and syntactic domains: the role of frequency,
the role of context, whether modular or interactive.

! Claim: the parallels derive from the fact that the syntactic


ambiguities are based on ambiguities on the lexical level.

Argument structure: capture facts about correlations between syntactic


and semantic info: specify categorial info about complements,
and thematic role info.  'This conjunction of syntactic and semantic
info in one representation captures interdependencies betwen these types
of info that are important for language professinga nd ambiguity
resolution (Boland & Tanenhaus 1991; FCarlson & Tanenhaus 1988, Stowe 1989).

X' theory is put into the lexicon: 'The lexicon is thus the level


at which syntactic processing takes place'.

Since it is clear that levels are not


independent,
connections between levels of lexical represtnation can be
exhititory or inhibitory. 
Ambiguity resolution is a constraint-satisfaction problem.
(Parallel is drawn to Bates and MacWhinney model).

Pieces of syntactic structure can be activated to differing


degrees.

Early on M seems to criticize the idea that meanings are fixed entries


that can be 'accessed'; instead she suggestss that meanings are
activated to varying degrees. (But her own representations seem fairly
fixed.)

M notes that not all contexts are equally constraining:


The next word in the sentences is [blank] vs I drink
my ocffee with cream and [blank].  She seems to attribute the
lack of context effects found by Swinney 1979 to the fact that
the contexts were not constraining enough.  TRUE??

She notes that lexical info seems to dominate over effects of contextual


constraints in lexical processing ('bottom-up' effects of Marseln-Wilson 1987).  This is attributed to the fact that contexts are less effective at
preselecting a possible alternative.

\medskip


MV/RR ambiguity:

Three types of verbs:


enjoyed is used much mre often as


a past tense than as a past participle: shold therefore
be easier to comprehend in a past tense construcion than a past participle.

examined more equaly balanced between past and pp

reviewed is used more frequently as a past participle than
as a past tense: therefore it shoudl act more like an unambiguious
pp such as taken

Findings after reanalyzing previous studies: all effects were


in the predicted direction (not clear how strong the findings
were, though).

Relative frequency of particular argument structures should have


a similar effect: push is more likely to be transitive;
move is more frequently intransitive.

\smallskip

Kawamoto's (1988, 1993) model suggest that
context is able to cause a single interpretation to be favored
only in cases where strong frequency asymmetries are not present.

\medskip


! NP/S ambiguity
Minimal Attachment predicts that NP interpretation should
be favored, because S is more complex phrase structure.
Can test frequency effects by looking at verbs which statistically
prefer the S arg structure, though. 

Such studies have had


mixed results.  M offers an explanation:
1) Trueswell 1993 note that many supposedly S-biased words  such
as pray, agree were
actually biased toward some other arg structure.

2) Low frequency verbs (e.g. hint) that take an S complement typically


prefer to have the that complementizer present, whereas
high frequency verbs (e.g. know) often omit that.
Target sentences normally omit that to make the sentence
more easily ambiguous: which creates oddness effects for verbs like
hint.

\medskip
! PP Attachment ambiguity: Not so clear what Minimal Attachment


predicts: depends on your fav theory of phrase structure.  Speakers
often prefer PP complement attachment.
M: different factors come into play here: the type of P involved
(one that often marks a complement, e.g. with, into or
one that often marks a modifier.
Also, does the verb obligatorily, or frequently require a PP complement?

Context effects seem to be most powerful in PP-attachment

\medskip

Juliano and Tanenhaus 1993 show that that at the beginning


of a sentence is more likely to be a determiner, and almost
never a complementizer; but that after a verb is
more likely to be a complementizer and not a determiner.
In reading-time experiments, subjects were extremely sensitive
to these contingent frequency effects.

ambiguity.


*!*Macken, Elizabeth, John Perry and Cathy Haas.


1993. Richly Grounding Symbols in ASL.
CSLI Report No. 93-180.
`` The use of richly grounding symbols [RGS's] does not imply that
ASL lacks the features of structure and productivity that
are the hallmarks of language. SEcond, the meaning of RGSs may be
conventional.  The correct contrast is between
symbls whose structure has a cognitively robust relation with
the structure of that which is symbolized, and hence easily
inferred and/or remembered, and symbols whose connection
with their meaning is arbitrary.  Third, richly grounded meaning
is found in the way we modify and combine symbols, as well
as in the basic symbols themselves." pg 16.

ASL is a dual-representation language: combines both arbitrary


signs and RGSs.

They note this can help explain Bellugi's observations that


citation forms often take twice as long as spoken words, but
the time to express a whole proposition is the same.

*!*McNally, Louise. Bare plurals in Spanish are interpreted


as properties. ms 1995. Universitat Pompeu Fabra.
Hi Louise,
 I just read through your paper, and I find it very clear
and well written.  I am the most interested in your
analogy to incorporation, which I find intriguing.

 I think it's probably common for languges


that allow incorporation to also allow either BPs
or BSs (bare singulars) with a property interpretation.
In fact, it may be that this is a logical (historical)
precursor to incorporation.  E.g. Persian has a productive
pattern of both BPs or BSs, and the incorporated cases
seem to be cases in which the BS and the verb have formed an
especially tight semantic bond, which is then mirrored
in the tighter syntactic bond.
(So I wouldn't necessarily set the two possibilties up
as two independent ways to satsify a single pragmatic
function :pg 13).

 I wonder what the relation between BSs and BPs is.


You could imagine only BSs occuring in truly incorporated forms
because of word-formation constraints (derivation preceeding
inflection).  But Persian allows free unincorporated objects to
be either BS or BP: both with a pretty darn close generic
interpretation.  I guess I'm just asking myself this out
loud: what is the sematnic difference in that case?

``[This] analysis suggests why BPs resemble incorporated nominals...


without requiring that they be incoporated in any interseing syntactic or morophological sense...incorporated nominals..and BPs would
resmble each other in their sematnic type---both interpeted
as properteis (as van Greenhoven 1993, 1995 proposes--and
therefore likely to
combine with predicate denoations via similar semantic
operations...speakers of
languages without morphological or syntactic incorporation
constructions would find use for other linguistic devices
(such as BPs with their special semantics) that would allow them
to approximate the pragmatic functions of incorporation. pg 13

*!*Miller, D. Gary. 1993. Complex Verb Formation.


Philadelphia:
John Benjamins Publishing.

A Complex Verb : ``oen that has undergone some sort of derivation to


alter the form, meaning, or argument structure of the base verb (or verb 'root').
For the most part, only affixation is treated..."

``syntactic morphologists generally relegate the `adjectival passive'


to the lexicon."

``This work takes the radical position that it is not accidental


that most data admit of either a syntactic or lexical, PS or non-PS
analysis, and that the reason for it is that both are likely to be valid - under diffrent
circumstances.

Reasons why all words are often claimed to be listed in lexicon:

lexical insertion has (at least in the past) been
claimed to insert a fully derived word into phrase structure. Supposedly, a fully
derived word is selcted from a list of completely derived words (the
Lexicon).
captures the intuition that there is a difference between
a real (existing) word and a possible word.
blocking requires that not only idiosyncratic forms be listed.
But synonyms in general are blocked, and Kiparsky, Hofmann, Sproat, Zwicky, DiScuillo an Williams show that blokcing
is not a specifically morphological principle, wherefore there is no necesary connection between
blocking and the lexicon.

derived words tend to acquire idiosyncratic meanings e.g. transmit: transmission (Aronoff 1976)


Listing whole words would account for the INHERITANCE of
irregularity by a derivative (Aronoff 1976).

Lexicalist Hypothesis: (Chomsky 1970): syntactic rules


cannot make refernce to any aspect f the internal structure of a word
This position is summarized by DiSciullo & Williams (1987:49)
as follows:
\begin{quote
Words are 'atomic' at the level of phrasal syntax and phrasal
smeantics. The words have features, or properties, but ehse featuers
have no structure, and the
relation of these features to the internal composition of the owrd
cannot be relevant in syntax - this is the thesis of the atomicity of words, or the lexical
integrity hypothesis of Chomsky (1970), WIlimans,..and numerous
others
{quote

Strong Lexicalist Hypothesis: fully inflected forms (provided by


lexical rules) are placed in phrase structure by lexical insertion.

Weak LExicalist Hypothesis (Interpretive Morphology): inflectional


operations are applied in the syntactic component (or later).

``Radical departures from the various lexicalist positions


are found in Sproat (1985), Baker (1988) and
Hale and Keyser (1991)":  Phrase STructure Morphology:

1) there is no separate morp0hological component

2) there are no Word Formation Rules

3) all morphology is essentially syntactic in the sense that


it is governed by grammatical rather than lexical principles and parameters

\subsection{Derivation vs Inflection

Derivation is semantically based, recursive, and non-suspendable;
Inflection is syntacially obligatory (automatic), non-recursive,
and suspendable in certain speech styles and with certain illnesses
Tyler & Nagy (1987): inflection causes overgeneralizations in
children, while these are rare with derivation
phonological rules can depend exculsively on inflection,
derivation and/or compounding
Derivation seems to feed inflection, but inflection does
not feed into derivation.  [But, this is not completely true (Dressler 1986)]
derivational affixes are generally shorter than lexical roots/stems, but longer than inflectional affixes
Derivational affixes evolve into inflectional more frequently
than the other way around.

Bybee (1985) views derivation and inflection on a continuum.


Bybee's COntinuum of Expression Units:

 lexical - derivational - inflectional- free grammatical - syntactic

(Miller doesn't buy it)
*!*Maling, Joan. 1993. Lexical Case and Middle Formation:
German vs Icelandic. ms. Brandeis.

(Beneficiary)


Goal args fail to undergo Middle Formation in both Grm and
Icelandic, irrespective of
their morphological case marking.  Lexical case-makring on a verb's object
is not a relevant factor (contra Fagan 1992).

The fabric washes well.


*He helps with difficulty.

Help takes a goal or ben argument

Evidence for ben/theme distinction:
{Our help/thanks to/*of the hostess went unacknowledged. (Wasow 1977)
\eenumsentence{ the student's rescue ambiguous: agt or theme
the student's help (unabiguous: agent only *goal

*!*Mohanan, Tara. 1994. Wordhood and Lexicality: Noun


Incorporation in Hindi. Submitted to NLLT

NI: noun combining with a verb to form a complex verb:


Mithun 1984, Hopper and Thompson 1984, Sadock (1980, 1991),
Baker(1988), DiSciullo and WIlliams(1987) and Rosen (1989)
are cited as general refs.

Agreement facts argue that the N must be treated syntactically


as an argument on par with the other args of the verb
(I think this is Baker's take, too).  At the same time, though,
NI is lexical in various ways.

Most NI sentences are actually ambiguous between an NI reading,


and a simple verb reading.  (e.g., "Anil will sell books," OR
"Anil will do book-selling.")

nothing may intervene between N and V in NI: not


subject, locative adjunct, or negative. (word order is
usually free in Hindi)
[certain things can intervene in Persian]

N cannot be modified, and modifier cannot


be stranded either: this is not predicted by Baker's account
of head-movement, or by Sadock's coanalysis account.
[same is true in Persian]
neither wh-words nor pronouns can be the N in NI:
``*what-selling" ``*this-selling": M attributes this fact
to the fact that wh-words and pronouns are maximal
projections, and N of NI is necessarily zero-level.
[would also seem to be ruled out by the naming pragmatic
constraint, though]
neither the N or the V can be gapped in a coordination
construction: ``*Anil does horse buying and Ram does -selling."
``*Anil does hourse-and Ram elephant-selling."
This is claimed to follow from the Lexical Integrity
Hypothesis: the categorial representation formed inthe
lexical modeule is not visible to principles of phrasal
organization. [M points out that adopting this principle
effectively rules out a head-movement analysis like
Baker's or a coanalysis like Sadock's as well].
neither N or V can be conjoined in NI: this is attributed
to the fact that lexical categories cannot be
conjoined in Hindi.
N doesn't bare an overt case clitic: but M claims N is
in nominative case: is nominative case is unmarked? how do
we know it's there at all?
Explanation for this is that clistics apply to phrasal
categories, not zero level categories.
evidence also comes from phonology: stress contours
NI can be input to lexical derivational N formation:
via
derivational suffix -vaalaa

Semantic/Pragmatic constraints on NI:

N must be generic or ``non-referential": it can only
refer to the class of entities denoted by the noun,not to the idividual
members of the class.  (M cites references that point out that
Ni is not necessarily accompanied by genericity or nonspecificity
(cf.Mohawk(mithun 1984), Eskimo(Sadock 1980).
the activity or process refered to by NI must be
``salient" or ``name-worthy"in what Hale and Keyser (1991:13)
call the ``cultural encyclopedia" of language users.
``\#clothes-tearing, \#grass-seeing, \#book-giving, \#book-lifting"
[In this section she notes \#kissed bride, vs unkissed bride
in Eng]
This also follows from idea that nameworthiness is a property
of lexical items (Hale & Keyser 1991: 13)

\bigskip
EVIDENCE FOR PHRASAL STATUS:

Agreement facts:

1) Verb agrees with the object iff the object is NOM, and


the subject is not NOM.

2) NOM case can only be determined after phrasal concatenation:


because phrasally concatenated model can assign DAT case to the
subject

3) V can agree with incorporated in NI


SOLN to the paradox: separate two dimensions of


syntactic info: grammatical functions (NI involves PRED
and OBJ) and grammatical categories (V0 -> N0 V0).

*!*Naigles, Letitia, Henry Gleitman and Lila Gleitman.


1993. Children Acquire Word Meaning Components from Syntactic
Evidence. In E. Dromi ed., Language and Cognition:
A Developmental Perspective. Human Development Vol. 5
104-140.
New Jersey: Ablex Publishing.

Frames:


 NP V NP PP: The elephant comes the giraffe towards the ark.

 NP V NP: The zebra goes the lion.

 NP V PP: The lion puts in the ark.

 NP V: The zebra brings.


51 2 yr. olds; 23 3yrs; 20 4 yrs; adults were given sentences


such as those above, as well as grammatical sentences, and asked
to act out what the sentence described.

Frame Compliance: scene acted out was in accord with the syntactic


frame, not the already known lexical semantics.

Verb Compliance: scene was acted out in accord with the previously


known sematnic implications of the verb itself

Other: the enactment is "wrong" in some other way.

\noindent Results: Mean Percent Frame Compliance as a Function of Frame Type and Age

\begin{tabular{lllll


Frame & 2 & 3 & 4 & Adult\\
NP V PP PP & - & 78.75 & 79.20 & 75.85\\
*The elephant comes the giraffe towards the ark & & & &\\
NP V NP & 69.15 & 70.45 & 71.65 & 50.00\\
*The zebra goes the lion & & & &\\
NP V PP & 60.40 & 63.85 & 70.45 & 30.40\\
*The lion puts in the ark & & & & \\  
NP V & 65.37 & 40.00 & 44.55 & 34.14\\
*The zebra brings & & & & \\
{tabular

Children show more Frame Compliance than adults, probably because


they performed "repair" on the ungrammatical sentnces where possible, interpreting, The zebra goes the lion as The zebra goes TO
the lion.

Frames with PPs were more likely to be Frame Compliant because


``the additional semantic info in the PPs simply makes it easier
to take a guess at what the whole sentence might mean." pg 128.

They assume that use in a syntactic frame reflects an additional


component to the verb's meaning (doing a little syntactic bootstrapping of their own, as they put it).

The assume: ``The number of nominal phrases and the number of


thematic roles in a clause must line up one-to-one (theta-crterion;
see Chomsky 1981)." (129)

The note that "word formation rules" are more likely to add


structure than to tear it down.

Where do the presumed correspondences come from? They assume


``there is sufficient cross-linguistic similarity in these linking rules
to get the learning procedure started.
For instance, the best guess from cross-linguistic inquiry
is that, in all, languages, the number of NPs in a snetence at teh
surface is a straightforward function of the logic of the verb concent...
there is an overwhelming tendency, corss-linguistically, for agents to appear as subejcts
and themes as direct objections, with other arguments appearing
in oblique cases." (pg 136-137)

*!*Nishimura, Yoshiki. ms 1995. Agentivity and Causation


in Cognitive  Linguistics.

Describes a prototype category of agentivity and


causative constructions.
(clearly written)

*!*Pesetsky, David. ms. Zero Syntax


[Adele: read Woodbury 1987 pg 688ff on discussion
against placeholders in syntax: cited in Knud's book]

*!*Polinksy, Maria and Isaac Kozinksy. 1992.


Ditransitive Constructions in Kinyarwanda: coding conflict or
syntactic doubling?  CLS 28. ed. by C. Canakis, G. Chan
and J. Denton. 426-439.
Coding Conflict: absolute identity in the marking of two or more
distinct grammatical, semantic or pragmatic functions by free
or bound segmental elements and/or by suprasegmental elts.

They argue against syntactic doubling, wherein two of the same


GR are found within a clause.
They look at Kinyarwanda and argue that the patient of ditransitive
applicatives is a DO, the recipient being an IO.

Range of applicatives ("ditransitives"):


{ Possessor Ascension: \\
man hold woman child \\
the man is holdingh te woman's child
{Benefactive: \\
woman read child book \\
the woman read the book to the child.
{Instrumental Advancement: \\
woman wash child soap\\
The woman washed the child with soap.
{Morphological causative:
woman wash-CAUS girl child \\
THe woman made the girl wash the child.

Prototypical ditransitives: the verb semantically requires a recipient:


give, show, offer, demand, request, ask, send, teach, explain,
promise: these require no verbal marking (neither do benefactives).

Evidence that the patient is DO, the recipient IO:

Conjunction Reduction:

"The cow kicked the woman's child and the child *the woman cried."

The patient has more controlling properties than the advanced/ascended NP.

*!*S. Riehemann, 1997 ms. Idiomatic Constructions in HPSG.


In JP Koenig, gert Webelhuth, Andreas Kathol (eds).

This paper explicates how phrasal idioms can be represted directly


in HPSG without assuming that their meaning is present in any (or all)
lexical items within the idiom. 

This paper represents an extremely valuable contribution to the theory, since


it provides a natural way of accounting for the intuitively phrasal but cleary
flexible nature of idioms.  It would also be a simple extension to account for
meaningful, phrasal, flexible constructions of more general types
such as locative inversion or the argument structure constructions
discussed in Goldberg 1995.

Below I offer some suggestions, mostly for clarification of the main points:

--I've never heard of the "cat among pigeons' idiom.    The author
might consider using the ``up the creek without a paddle" or ``butterflies
in one's stomach" mentioned later instead.

--I don't understand the argument based on examples in (3) that


"loose ends" is not an argument of "tie."  Is the author assuming
that subjects are not arguments?  It would seem that the raised
or passivized argument of a verb is still an argument, which would
make the examples in (3) unremarkable on a lexical account.

--SR cites several problems with lexical approaches:


 -would seem to predict that the idiomatic meaning of the word coould
appear elsewhere.

 -would seem to have problems with the fact that parts of idioms often


specify adjectives, adjuncts, and determiners not normally subcategorized for.

--Nice dicussion of Pullum 1993 who suggests that idioms are represented


semantically by meaning postulates basically.

 -SR notes that inference is too strong, would predict idiomatic meaning available


for:
  The cat and the dog are out of the laundry bag. (-> the cat is out of the bag)

 - Also, psycholinguistic evidence about the processing of idioms suggests the


literal interpretation is not generally accessed first [should give
a citation here:  e.g. Ray Gibbs 1993 Poetics of Mind].

--"OSU" in footnote 5 should be unabbreviated.

--The idea proposed in footnote 8 is interesting and has precedent in
Lakoff 1987 and Goldberg 1995.

--While the proposal is exciting and interesting, it could stand to be explicated


a little more clearly.

SR proposes Underspecified Phrasal Semantics (UPS approach), following Copestake


1994.

phrases have set-valued feature WORDS, containing all of the words in the phrase

--It is claimed to be a virtue of the theory that the words of
the idiom are not assigned an existence outside the idiom, but
that would seem to make their semantic/phonological similarity
to existing words seem to be a coincidence.   (pg 1) Or is
this intended to mean that there are no words *with the relevant
idiomatic meaning* outside of the idiom?  Given the following, this
seems to be what is meant, but it should be stated more clearly.

--The words have their ordinary meanings, ``overwritten during compilation


by skeptical default unification" [a word about what this is would be
helpful],
or maybe they don't because ``all this can be precompiled..[so] that the
literal meanings are not present anywhere in the parse." pg 8 note 6.
(see below *)

--Only the semantic relationships between the words are specified: beans is the


undergoer of spilling, which indirectly fixes the syntax to some extent:
allows modification, ``movement".

--It is noted that the words in the set do not all have to be sisters when they


appear overtly.  They are related semantically, not syntactically, but does
this violate some kind of locality condition nonetheless?  Maybe not.

-- Nondecomposable idioms are given without specifying meanings for


individual words *and* by specifying syntactic form.
By not specifying the semantic relationships among the words, it is clearly
necessary to specify the syntactic relationships if the idiom is to be expressed at all.
However it's not clear to me that this follows from the proposal, since it would
seem to be possible that only a set of word forms could be specified which
might then occur overtly in any configuration whatsoever (The kick was a bucket).
Is there some general mechanism that avoids this?

-- ``The necessary information about the literal words is available


and can be used to restrict syntactic variation"
--Is info about literal words available (see above *)
--assuming it is in fact available, how does that restrict the syntactic variation exactly?

-- Idiom families are said to be handleable because the literal


meanings are accessible [again see *]

( The feature CXCONT is used in teh ERGO grammar to encode the semantic contribution


of constructions.)

*!*Rosen, Sara Thomas. 1989. Two Types of Noun


Incorporation: A Lexical Analysis. Language 65 2.
With Mithun and DiSciullo & WIlliams, she argues that NI
is a lexical process (against Baker and Sadock).

Two types of NI:

 Compound NI: involve simple compounding: one argument of the simple verb is satisfied
within the verb.   (Mithun's first 3 classes) (e.g. Engl "meat-eater")

the arg structure of the simple verb is


changed to become intransitive 
no stranding of modifiers
no doubling outside verb

Classifier NI:


can still take an object: the incorporated N is semantically
like a classifier of the object. 

Simple and complex verb's arg structure is the same: can still


take an object

Languages with this type of


NI are said to allow 'stranding' of modifiers (null-head modifiers).
doubling outside of verb

Compounding shoudl be invisible to the syntax.

[This typology doesn't seem to allow for transitive CPs which are not
classifier type: Mithun's type II]

R notes that there is a subject/non-subject asymetry: with


deep subjects not incorporating: instrumentals incorporate
in Nahuatl, means phrases incorporate in Niuean, and some locatives
incorporate in Samoan--non of these phrases is ever a DO.

Goals and benefactives never incorporate in any language.

*!*Sag, Ivan A. ms (1994 Dec) English Relative Clause
Constructions

Argues that the move away from construction-specific rules has


led to a sacrifice of precision.

``this method [of multiple inheritance hierarchy] has a significant


untapped potential forthe treatment of grammatical ocnstructions as
well, a point well appreciated by the closely related ongoing work within
the tradition of Construction Grammar..." pg1.

Notes to Ivan:

Dear Ivan,
 I just finished your paper--I thought it was very nice!
Here are some minor comments:

pg 3, 1st PP: explain "sponsorship" or maybe footnote this.

pg 5: The Korean verb marking is nice motivation for the verb being
the head of the relative clause.
Since you claim later (pg 20-21) that when there is an overt complementizer,
*it* is the head of the RC, would you predict that no lng would mark
its RC verbs (like Korean) and have overt complementizers? 

pg 6: To make contact with ConGram, you could mention Jean-Pierre's


thesis as another reference for multiple inheritance of lexical items.

The sign is defined just like the construction in ConGram:


a pairing of form and meaning.  The difference in terminology
is kind of telling, though, since we've heretofore largely
concentrated on the phrasal patterns to almost the exclusion of
the lexicon (but see Rhodes' CLS paper on morphology in Congram, JP's work),
whereas work in HPSG has come at form-meaning pairings from the Sausurrian
"sign" angle.

Pg 9: Work in ConGram has discussed multiple inheritance for


phrasal patterns (e.g. George's "There"-constructions paper in WFDT,
Fillmore & Kay ms, chapter 4 of my book).

(You might spell out "daughters" for DTRS once)

Pg 10: middle PP: you mention that [VAL-D elist] is a default
specification.  Does that mean you are assuming normal mode
and not complete inheritance?  

 This question is of some interest to those of us working in ConGram, since


Chuck, Paul and JP adopt complete inheritance because it is more
constrained, whereas George and I prefer normal or default inheritance,
since you can capture more types of relations.

pg 20: treating "that" as a finite verbal head of the RC is a stretch for me.

pg 26: Quirk's observation is not specific to postnominal modifiers:

 \#arrived guests


  recently arrived guests

It seems that change of location predicates are not generally good


as modifiers (at least without additional adverbial help):

 \#moved in couple


 recently moved in couple

pg 26: when you say,

 "we should be able to explain linguistic systems
 wherever possible in terms of independently known aspects of cognition,
 particularly categorization and constraints in domains other than language..."

do you mean that the classification in terms of sorts is supposed to


be a type of general categorization?  If so, then normal mode
inheritance may be more accurate, since people seem to categorize in terms
of prototypes and extensions from them.  Default inheritance seems to
capture that better than complete inheritance.

It may be outside the scope of this paper, but have you thought


about how to handle resumptive pronouns in RCs?  It seems they might
cause problems for the Valence Principle.

Typos:
pg 6: 2nd to last PP: "With each sort COME certain..."


      add period to PP
pg 8: 1st PP: "phrases...as feature STRUCTURE that serve"

pg 10: you sometimes use "hd-valence-ph" and sometimes abbreviate to


"hd-val-ph"

pg 11: footnote 9: "one important CHANGES"

*!*Sag, Ivan A. and Janet Dean Fodor. 1994. Extraction
without Traces. in WCCFL 13.

They debunk putative evidence for WH-traces as syntactic


entities:

Wanna Contraction: "wanna" does not contract if there is


a trace intervening between want and to. They note that
a nominative trace does not prevent contraction:

{
 Who does Kim think WH-trace is (think's) beneath contempt?

Bresnan proposed that the 's is a proclitic on beneath
rather than a postclitic on think, but they argue
against that on phonological grounds.

! Floated quantifiers:

{*How satisfied do you think they were all [ ]?
Following Brodie and Dowty and Brodie (1984), they argue that
floated quantifiers be treated as base-generated adjoined modifiers:
not moved elts at all.

Psycholinguistic evidence: antecedent activation occurs


at the verb and at the trace position. Following Fodor (1993)
they point out that  no pyscholinguistic finding could even in princpile
qualify as evidence for empty constituents unless it were
established that the data pertained to the syntactic
processing or representation of the sentene and not the
semantic.  The parser detects a gap, but that doesn't mean that
the parser detects a phonologically null syntactic entity.

They argue conversely that Pickering and Barry's putative


evidence against a syntactic gap is also not conclusive.

*!*Schmerling, Susan.  1973. Subjectless Sentences and the Notion of


Surface structure.  CLS 9 577-586

\eenumsentence{ Seems like the class always wakes up five minutes


before the bell rings.
Guess I should have been more careful
Going to lunch?

differ from fragments in that they require no preceeding discourse.


Perception verbs:


\eenumsentence{ Looks like an accident
Sounds like another ghost
Smells like hot metal
Tastes like almonds
Feels like real silk.

Modals:
{Must/might/could/may be an accident up ahead

`` Wastebasket class":
\eenumsentence{ Happens that way all the time
*Happens that way close at ten
Turns out you can't do that in Texas
Seems you can't do that in Texas.

(Almost no analysis here)

``there is some elusive element of spontaneity and implusiveness involved
in uttering them." pg 583
\eenumsentence{ Guess I should be going
*Guesses he should be going
*think I should be going
Think I'l have anohter cup of coffee
Wish I hadn't done that
Gotta be going
*Hafta be going.

\eenumsentence{ ??Got a lot of nerve.


Got a lot of nerve, doesn't he?/I'd say/eh?

*!*Slobin, Dan I. 1997.  The Orgins of Grammaticalicizable Notions:


Beyond the Indidivual Mind.  In Dan I. Slobin (ED) The Crosslinguistic
study of Language Acquisition: Vol. 5. Expanding the Contexts.
Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

Dan argues that there is a cline bewteen open and closed class lexical


items and that we do not need to posit innate mechanisms to account for
the cline.

*!*Slobin, Dan I. 1982.  Universal and Particular


in the acquisition of Language.
In Eric Wanner and Lila R. Gleitman (eds.) Language Acquisition: The State of the Art.  New York: Cambridge University
Press. 129-170.

Different languages differ in the ease of acquisition of different


subsystems.

Word order and adpositions in particular are studied.

Operating Principles: predispositions to perceive speech
and construct formal systems in particular ways (Slobin 1973)

>From previous work:


``Surface marking which is `overt' and `clear' is more easily discovered and


acquired by the child"

``...postposed markers (sufffixes and postpositions) are more salient than


preposed markers"

Here proposes that sentence processing is facilitated by local


cues: signals to underlying menaing which occur at localized points in the sentences.  E.g. inflections to indicate grammatical relations
are easier than word order.

Also, separate clauses are easier than particles which


conflate several notions or nominalizations which condense
entire clauses.

``On lexical level, semantic clarity of forms and a minimum of


lexical diversity facilitate acquisition"
*!*Sweetser, Eve. 1987.  Metaphorical Models of
Thought and Speech: a comparison of historical directions and metaphorical
mappings in the two domains.

\eenumsentence{ report $<$  to carry back (again) (Latin)


refer $<$  to carry back (again) (Latin)

Traugott (1985), Traugot and Dasher (1985):

mental state, speech act $<$ physical location/motion

Sweetser:


Explanation:
Both mental processing and conversations can be understood
in terms of a metaphor for travel:
\eenumsentence{ walk over/walk about
think about/think over
talk over/talk about

speech act senses $<$ physical location/motion

Don't find:  mental state $<$ speech act

Traugott (1982): expressive $<$ textual $<$ propositional


[Use
{THE car of the 21st C $<$ the car $<$ that car
{epistemic $<$ root
]

Particular mental state is often a preconidtion for the


felicitous performance of a speech act:
\eenumsentence{ one must have mentally certified (made
certain) before one can certify its truth to others
mental observation is  a precondition for observing
``making a remark"
mental recognition is a precondition for giving a person
the floor

Decision-making is mentally spearting the chosen option from the rejected option.


{decide (Lat decaedo ``cut off from")

Categorization is putting concepts into sets. 


\eenumsentence{ distinguish (Lat. Di(s) ``apart")
confuse (Lat con+fundere ``pour together, mix")
I can't tell them apart
I can't tell one from another

Reasoning as building a logical object:


\eenumsentence{ suppose $<$ Lat sub+ponere ``put under"
hypthesize $<$ Gr hypo+thesis ``under + putting"

Argument As Physical Combat:


\eenumsentence{ concede $<$ Lat concedere ``to yield, to give up"
insist $<$ Lat, ``stand in/on, stay"
[notice it has a force-dynamic element]
convince $<$ Lat con+vincere ``(intensifier+concquire"
TODAY: one is gaining/losing ground in an argument
can hit below the belt
someone brought out hte heavy altillery

*!*Thrasher, Randolph Hallet Jr. 1974.  U of Michigan dissertation


Morgan (1972) discourse fragments in 5 minutes: require previous discourse
context.

Present cases are distinguished from the following in NOT requiring special context:


\eenumsentence{ Must be broken
Probably hasn't gotten home from work yet
Long discussion in chapter 1.

Bolinger The Imperative in English (no date given):


\eenumsentence{ like it?
care to come along?
tell the differnce?

\eenumsentence{ Gotta go now


See you next Tues
Too bad about old charlie
No need to get upset about it
Been in Ann arbor long?
Ever et a chance to use your Dogrib?
Ever get to Japan, look me up
Good thing we didnt' run into anyone we know
Last person I expected to meet was John
Wife wants to go to the mountains this year. pg 5

Subjects (I, you, there, it and aux's, if, articles are dropped.

ommission from initial position
used only in informal contexts
only ``redundant" elements can delete (meaning must be recoverable)
grammatical, not lexical, information is deleted
must occur in face to face encounter (or as if face to face)

\eenumsentence{ Who are you rooming with? \\


Boy I went to high school with [ok?  seems topical...]
Why do you have to go home?
Son's sick.

Hints at relation of htis type of deletion with that found in newspapers, telegrams, signs. pg 21-23.


Main difference: place of deletion is more restricted in present case.

T argues for actual deletion because reflexives can occur in fragment.

``the choice has been narrowed to deciding between generating subjectless fragments
as part of the grammar of Enlgih or having them generated by a special fragment component
tacked on to the end of it." pg 33

Reasons for creating them as part of grammar: 1) they refer to grammatical elements


! Article deletion:

``articles in any other position than at the front of the sentence do not delete" pg 36

Modification of N sometimes encourages deletion:


\eenumsentence{ *? Boy is at the door.
(a) Boy who says he's a student of yours is at the door.
(The) Boy who called earlier is at the door.
[In these cases the modification makes it clear that speaker is INTRODUCING the boy]

Dummy but not anaphoric it and there delete


\eenumsentence{ TOo bad you lost
More than one way to skin a cat.

Not all dummy subjects delete.  Hedges, quantification are suggested to help deletion.


``it is also obvious that the totally unexplored are of conversational expectation is


involved.  ...if your guest commented that he was thirsty or really hot..":
(there's) beer in the refridgerator.

Avoidance of ambiguity:


Deletion is blocked if remaining fragment looks more like a simple NP or an imperative
than an S. pg 41:
{*(I'll) try to leave as soon as possible

Stressed elements do not delete.


{*Hey Mike.  Turn now.

\subsection{chapter 3: I and you

\subsection{chapter 4: no title

Possessive pronouns can be deleted in conversation:


\eenumsentence{ Bill. Wife's on the phone.
Got to go. Kids are waiting in the car.
Bill's not coming in. Son just called to say he has the flu.
pg 83

{(my) head is really throbbing. pg 86

Permission statements or reports of permission allow my,your to delete:
{(my your *his) wife can go home tomorrow

"Pronoun must be initial position" Notice not just subject below:

{Wife and kids getting used to life in Ann Arbor? pg 83 \\
*Are wife and kids getting used to life in Ann Arbor

For some speakers, all of the possessive determiner deletion is implossible.

``the variation gives support to Roos' squishiness principle. In fact, there seems to
be a complete heirarchy starting with auxilary verbs adn running to possessive pronouns." pg 88

Hierarchy:


{ aux $>$ dummy subj $>$ if $>$ subj pronouns $>$ articles $>$ possessive pronouns

Not quite true to say INITIAL position:


\eenumsentence{ Bigger they are, harder they fall.
if you don't get started, light'll turn red on you
]item when you get a minute, like ot have a word iwth you
This time next month, won't be able to buy beef at any price
After class, you going to be free
can't go otu like that.  Hair's a mess, sweatshirt's on inside out, socks don't
match, and your face isn't even washed. pg 89

``Rapport deletion" (pg 99):

{Gotta match?
is abrupt, even rude.  But ``it is the custom of some people to use such language with strangers..


tải về 302.24 Kb.

Chia sẻ với bạn bè của bạn:
1   2   3   4   5   6   7   8   9   10




Cơ sở dữ liệu được bảo vệ bởi bản quyền ©hocday.com 2024
được sử dụng cho việc quản lý

    Quê hương